Actions

Difference between revisions of "Deliberation"

From Deliberative Democracy Institiute Wiki

(Open Discussion)
(Open Discussion)
Line 160: Line 160:
 
==Settings of Deliberation==
 
==Settings of Deliberation==
 
===Open Discussion===
 
===Open Discussion===
A discussion that open a series of questions about a topic(see Kaner 2007<ref>[http://knowledgecenter.completionbydesign.org/sites/default/files/198 Kaner 2007.pdf Kaner, S., Lind, L., Toldi, C., Fisk, S., & Berger, D. (2007). Facilitator’s Guide to Participatory Decision-Making (2nd ed., p. 363). San Francisco: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.]</ref>)
+
A discussion that open a series of questions about a topic(see Kaner 2007<ref>[http://knowledgecenter.completionbydesign.org/sites/default/files/198_Kaner_2007.pdf Kaner, S., Lind, L., Toldi, C., Fisk, S., & Berger, D. (2007). Facilitator’s Guide to Participatory Decision-Making (2nd ed., p. 363). San Francisco: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.]</ref>)
  
 
===Converging Discussion===
 
===Converging Discussion===

Revision as of 04:06, 11 February 2014

aspects of deliberation

Theories of Deliberation

Cohen Joshua

From [1]

The public good and not the sector good:

Based on Rawl's justice: In a well-ordered democracy, political debate is organized around alternative conceptions of the public good. So an ideal pluralist scheme, in which democratic politics consists of fair bargaining among groups each of which pursues its particular or sectional interest, is unsuited to a just society[2]Citizens and parties operating in the political arena ought not to ‘take a narrow or group-interested standpoint’ (p. 360). And parties should only be responsive to demands that are ‘argued for openly by reference to a conception of the public good’ (pp. 226, 472).Public explanations and justifications of laws and policies are to be cast in terms of conceptions of the common good (conceptions that, on Rawls’s view, must be consistent with the two principles of justice), and public deliberation should aim to work out the details of such conceptions and to apply them to particular issues of public policy (p. 362).

In debate and common disccusions in the Knesset, parties are arguing for their narrow intrests, and not the common good. Deliberation should help a common good resulotions.

In a just society political opportunities and powers must be independent of economic or social position:

It should be taken care that the political decisions are not influenced by concentrations of money and social class[3]

The development of of political competence:

Third, democratic politics should be ordered in ways that provide a basis for selfrespect,that encourage the development of a sense of political competence, and that contribute to the formation of a sense of justice.it should fix ‘the foundations for civic friendship and [shape] the ethos of political culture’ (Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice (Cambridge. Mass.: Harvard University. p. 234).

Sum: When properly conducted, then, democratic politics involves public deliberation focused on the common good, requires some form of manifest equality among citizens,and shapes the identity and interests of citizens in ways that contribute to the formation of a public conception of common good.

Five defentions of Deliberative process

  1. A Continuous system for governing the group: A deliberative democracy is an ongoing and independent association, whose members expect it to continue into the indefinite future.
  2. To their deliberation there are results: The members of the association share (and it is common knowledge that they share) the view that the appropriate terms of association provide a framework for or are the results of their deliberation. They share, that is, a commitment to coordinating their activities within institutions that make deliberation possible and according to norms that they arrive at through their deliberation. For them, free deliberation among equals is the basis of legitimacy.
  3. Plurality of minds: A deliberative democracy is a pluralistic association. The members have diverse preferences, convictions and ideals concerning the conduct of their own lives. While sharing a commitment to the deliberative resolution of problems of collective choice (D2), they also have divergent aims, and do not think that some particular set of preferences, convictions or ideals is mandatory.
  4. Connection between disicions and results as source of legitmecy: Because the members of a democratic association regard deliberative procedures as the source of legitimacy, it is important to them that the terms of their association not merely be the results of their deliberation, but also be manifest to them as such. They prefer institutions in which the connections between deliberation and outcomes are evident to ones in which the connections are less clear.
  5. Every body is capble of deliberating: The members recognize one another as having deliberative capacities, i.e. the capacities required for entering into a public exchange of reasons and for acting on the result of such public reasoning.

Three steps of Deliberation

For a deliberative process there are three steps:

  1. There is a need to decide on an agenda.
  2. To propose alternative solutions to the problems on the agenda.Supporting those solutions with reasons.
  3. Conclude by settling on an alternative.

Priciples of Deliberation

  1. Deliberation is free. No other force then reason can be used.
  2. Parites should use reason to explain their motives and solutions.
  3. All parties are equal.
  4. Deliberation strive to achive rationaly motivated consensus. If not, it will reach majority role by voting.

Democratic assessment of collaborative planning processes‏

Creating of SON

Habermas: The theoretical foundation of our measure of discourse quality is Habermas’(1981, 1990, 1991, 1992, 1995, 1996) discourse ethics is the principle of universalism, which holds that a norm is valid only if everyone who is potentially affected by the norm accepts its consequences, including any anticipated negative side effects. The acceptance of norms cannot be imposed in an authoritarian manner. Rather, individuals ought to consent to those norms, and this is done through a process of argumentation and persuasion. This process of discourse constitutes ‘communicative action:’ individuals give and criticize reasons for holding or rejecting particular validity claims, so that universally valid norms can be discovered through reason. (Taken from [4])

Ethics

Dahl’s five criteria for evaluating democratic processes have been widely accepted, at least among students of democracy (Dahl, 1979, 1998; see Habermas[5], Saward[6]).The five criteria are[7] (taken from[8]):

  1. Effective participation
  2. Voting equality
  3. Enlightened understanding
  4. Control of the agenda
  5. Inclusion of all adults

Measuring Deliberation

For review look at[9], and look at my mind map based on the above.

Micro-analytic approaches study the quality of deliberation through closely analyzing the content of participants’ comments during the deliberative process. The macro-analytic approach, in turn, asks coders to make summary judgments of the discussion as a whole.

Studies using direct measures focus on the actual process of deliberation, while studies using indirect measures assess deliberation based on either antecedents (for instance, by measuring the extent to which conditions necessary for deliberation are met) or outcomes of the discussion (for example, by measuring post-deliberation changes in participants. ’ preferences).

Direct Measurments

Those that measure deliberation directly examine the deliberative discussion to determine the extent to which the discussion corresponds to theoretical conceptions of deliberation.

The most common direct measurement of deliberation in small groups is what we call discussion analysis, which includes a range of methods used to systematically evaluate the communication engaged in during a deliberative discussion (also called micro-measurments). Another common method used for the direct study of deliberation is to ask participants for their own assessments of the deliberative process (also called macro-measurments). This is typically done through post-deliberation surveys or interviews in which respondents reflect on their experience as a participant and answer questions about the deliberative quality of the discussion. The case study will be the final direct approach we review. Discussion.

DQI: Measuring Political Deliberation: A Discourse Quality Index (2003), based on Habermas theories[10].

Bachtiger 2009

An attmept to improve DQI[11]

  • Typr I deliberation
    • Equality - measured by precentage of participation and number of words for each participent (mean?)
    • Rational Justification:
      • no justification
      • inferior justification where the linkage between reasons and conclusion is tenuous.
      • qualified justification where a linkage between reasons and conclusion is made.
      • sophisticated justification (broad) where at least two complete justifications are given.
      • sophisticated justification (in depth) when at least one justification is explored in-depth, i.e., a problem is examined in a quasi-scientific way from various viewpoints.
    • Common Good Orientation: The importance of referring to the common good is mainly stressed by deliberative theorists drawing on Rawls.
      • whether arguments are cast in terms of narrow group or constituency interests.
      • whether there is neutral reference or mixed reference (i.e., reference to both narrow group interest and common good).
      • whether there is a reference to the common good. With regard to the common good, we focus both on the common good stated in utilitarian terms, i.e. as the best solution for the greatest number of people
      • the common good expressed through the difference principle, i.e. the common good is served when the least advantaged in a society are helped (Rawls 1971).
    • Respect Toward Demands and Counterarguments
      • speakers degrade.
      • treat neutrally.
      • value.
      • agree
    • Interactivity: whether participants refer to other participants and to other participants’ arguments.
    • Cunstructive Politics: This indicator is based upon the principal goal of type I deliberation to reach consensus.
      • positional politics form the lowest level.
      • alternative proposals, i.e. proposals that attempt to mediate but that do not fit the current agenda.
      • consensus appeals.
      • mediating proposals.
    • Trthfulness: There is no way to mesure it by direct obsevations.
  • Type II Deliberation:
    • Story Telling: “story-telling” is the most important component of alternative forms of communication. They demonstrate that “story-telling” can play a central role in deliberative processes: “we find that narrative’s conventional openness to interpretation – in essence, its ambiguity – proved a surprising deliberative resource for people with marginalized points of view.”[12]. They use "sourcing" acording to Stormer-Galley[13]
    • Deliberative Negoatiations:
      • deliberative negoatiations: using only arguments.
      • non-deliberative negoatiations: using threts or implicit threts.count whether a speech contains threats or promises[14].

Diffrent methods of deliberation should have differnt expectd values in the fifferent parts.

From Bechtiger 2009[15]



Holtinger (In German)[16]

Stromer-Galley: read[17]

Indirect Measurments

Studies using indirect measures assess deliberation based on either antecedents (for example, by measuring the extent to which conditions necessary for deliberation are met) or outcomes of the discussion (for example, by measuring post-deliberation changes in participants).

Type I and Type II Deliberation

Type II Deliberation

In the past decade, there have been several attempts to strip deliberation off its rationalist bias. Difference democrats and feminists allege that deliberative theorists’ focus on rational, dispassionate discussion creates a stifling uniformity and constrains deliberation (e.g., Sanders 1997[18]). According to Sanders, many (usually) disadvantaged people do not engage in idealized forms of deliberation, which suits only a privileged few. Therefore, difference democrats and feminists stress the need to admit wider forms of communication – such as testimony, storytelling, or rhetoric – to avoid these constraints. Following Mansbridge et al. (2009)[19] self-interest must also have a place in deliberative models: “Including self-interest in deliberative democracy reduces the possibility of exploitation, introduces information that facilitates reasonable solutions and the identification of integrative outcomes, and also motivates vigorous and creative deliberation. Excluding self-interest from deliberative democracy is likely to produce obfuscation.” Empirical research also demonstrates that bargaining - representing the central instrument of expressing and accomplishing self-interest in negotiations - and deliberation usually go together in reality[20].

Layers of Coordination

There are several layers of coordination that are needed in order to achieve agreement:

  1. Communication medium - The medium of coordination should be adjusted to serve the communication betweeen the members.
  2. SON - In order to cooperate, people have to understand each other. The Social Objects Network (SON), is the way people encode the perceive the world. To coordinate well, they have to adjust their SONs.
  3. Culture - Different cultures have different communication styles. When participant do not share the same culture, they may not understand other culture codes (SONs) and the appropriate manners, according to that culture, therefore resulting mistrust and disgust, which will result failure to cooperate.
  4. Values - Values are the way we evaluate the outcome of our decisions. For instance, some may evaluate "The bottom line (monetary gains)", while other may evaluate the well-being of the workers and customers. Those two different values may create disagreement about the preferred options that should be taken.
  5. Interests - Any outcome from the options that the group may take, may harm or gain any one of her members (or the community that the group serve). So members will try to evaluate the gains and harms and will search for the best option that will serve their interests. Many times members will try to use "hidden agendas" discourse to divert the options taken to achieve selfish interests. Therefore deliberation experts say it is important to know each member interests and put them on the open so no hidden agendas will subvert the decision.

Metaconsensus

Dryzek and mm think that meta consensus should be gained based on how to conduct the deliberation process.[21]

Systematic Approach To Deliberation

Justification of Deliberation

justification of deliberation

The legitimecy of a system of deliberation and decision making, depend on it's efficiency in promoting long-term prosperty of the members of the group. A good system will be a one that need low investment of resources by the citizens in the act of decision making and achieve fast decisions and yeald decisions that enable larger parts of the populations to flourish.

Deliberation systems have three main functions, according to the the writers of Deliberative systems[22].

  1. Epistemic - Good deliberation should produce well corroborated and inter-subjective SON. It should produced unbiased decisions, and eliminate as much as possible group thinking. The decision by the citizens will be well informed.
  2. Ethic - Good deliberation will take the needs of all members and will produce optimal inclusive solutions. A solution that will enable all members to feel that they are benefiting from being a members in the group.
  3. Democratic - People will engage shared challenges, will recognize and understand on other citizens, and will be responsible for the acts taken by the state. This will make the citizens influential, involved and responsible. It will strength the social capital and the education of the citizens. It will strive to get as much inclusive solution so that everybody will feel that she or he is been concerned as important and equal citizen.

On using Experts in Deliberation

Although experts are sometimes crucial for deliberation, because they hold more corroborated SON, there are some concern that should be addresses when expert are taking part in a deliberation. Expert may harm deliberation in those aspects:

  • Epistemically, delegation of deliberation to expert can promote citizen ignorance.
  • Experts may be biased (as was suggested by Loerenz et al.[23])
  • The world view of the experts can be very narrow, and may have low representation of variety of important SON to the decision making. The may have lack of emotional perspective of the population, or may ignore ethical or democratic principles.
  • Experts can be influenced by some major school of thoughts that prevail in the academy, which is not part of the wider population ideas.
  • Expert may be part of well educated elite which are not good representative of the whole public, and may promote decision in the lite of their elite world-view.
  • Experts may also lack the will or the understanding of reaching the ability of a group to act, or to reach high degree of consensus. Groups needs some inner adjustment to happen, so the can act. Some more able people need should be addressed, so they will want to move the group towards it's goals. Or a group should reach high degree of consensus to avoid grudge between groups. Experts decisions may not take these factors into account.
  • Experts may need to distance themselves from the some times half-backed thoughts of populism, but they should also avoid alienation from the crowds.
  • Exclusion of non-experts from the process of decision making may threatens the foundations of democracy itself, as the rule by the people.
  • Even if Experts do not include non-experts in the process of building the models from which deliberation is growing, can shift the decision making, and let experts control the decision making.

Epistemic Considerations

Epistemology of Deliberation

the problem of coordination

Settings of Deliberation

Open Discussion

A discussion that open a series of questions about a topic(see Kaner 2007[24])

Converging Discussion

Due to the problem of selecting from multiple of choices (eg Condercent-arrow problem of social choice[25][26]) we need converging discussion.

Releted Matrials

Limitations on group size

large groups on-line deliberation

MO deliberation

face to face agreements

Distortions in Reason

For unloigical and intutive reasoning, see Intuitive Decision Making in "Decision Making"

hidden agenda

Psychological considerations

FFFF and deliberation

Settings that promote system 2 discussion

methods of deliberation

deliberative polls

online deliberation

Criticism on deliberation

criticism on deliberation

See Also

the science of story telling

References

  1. Cohen, J. (1989). Deliberation and democratic legitimacy. Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy, 342.
  2. Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice (Cambridge. Mass.: Harvard University.p360-361
  3. Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice (Cambridge. Mass.: Harvard University. pp. 225–6, 277–8; 1982, pp.42–3.
  4. Steenbergen, Marco R., et al. "Measuring political deliberation: a discourse quality index." Comparative European Politics 1.1 (2003): 21-48.(p.25)
  5. Habermas, Jürgen. "Between Facts and Norms, Cambridge." Polity 213 (1996).‏
  6. Saward, Michael. "Making democratic connections: Political equality, deliberation and direct democracy." Acta Politica 36.4 (2001): 361-379.‏
  7. Dahl A., R. (2000). On Democracy (1st ed., p. 224). New Haven: Yale University Press.
  8. Agger, Annika, and Karl Löfgren. "Democratic assessment of collaborative planning processes." Planning Theory 7.2 (2008): 145-164.‏
  9. Black, Laura W., et al. "Methods for analyzing and measuring group deliberation." Sourcebook of political communication research: Methods, measures, and analytical techniques (2011): 323-345.
  10. Steenbergen, Marco R., et al. "Measuring political deliberation: a discourse quality index." Comparative European Politics 1.1 (2003): 21-48.‏
  11. Bachtiger, A., et al. "Measuring deliberation 2.0: standards, discourse types, and sequenzialization." ECPR General Conference, Potsdam. 2009.
  12. [http://www.socsci.uci.edu/~polletta/Articles%20and%20Book%20Chapters_files/2006%20polletta%20lee%20telling%20stories%20asr.pdf Polletta, F., & Lee, J. (2006). Is telling stories good for democracy? Rhetoric in public deliberation after 9/11. American Sociological Review, 71(5), 699–721. p.710
  13. Stromer-Galley, J. (2007). Measuring deliberation’s content: A coding scheme. Journal of Public Deliberation, 3(1), 12.
  14. Holzinger, K. (2001). Kommunikationsmodi und Handlungstypen in den Internationalen Beziehungen. Anmerkungen zu einigen irref{ü}hrenden Dichotomien. Zeitschrift F{ü}r Internationale Beziehungen, 243–286.
  15. Bachtiger, A., Shikano, S., Pedrini, S., & Ryser, M. (2009). Measuring deliberation 2.0: standards, discourse types, and sequenzialization. In ECPR General Conference, Potsdam (pp. 5–12).
  16. Holzinger, Katharina. 2001. Kommunikationsmodi und Handlungstypen in den Internationalen Beziehungen. Anmerkungen zu einigen irreführenden Dichotomien. Politische Vierteljahreschrift 42, 414-446
  17. Stromer-Galley, J. (2007). Measuring deliberation’s content: A coding scheme. Journal of Public Deliberation, 3(1), 12.
  18. Sanders, L. M. (1997). Against deliberation. Political Theory, 25(3), 347–376.
  19. Mansbridge, J. J. (2009). Deliberative and non-deliberative negotiations.
  20. Risse, T. (2004). Global governance and communicative action. Government and Opposition, 39(2), 288–313.
  21. Dryzek, John S. and Simon J. Niemeyer. 2006. Reconciling pluralism and consensus a spolitical ideals. American Journal of Political Science, 50, 634–49.
  22. Parkinson, J., & Mansbridge, J. (Eds.). (2012). Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale, Cambridge University Press. p.10-12
  23. Lorenz et al., How social infulence can underminr the wisdom of the crowds effect, 2011, PNAS
  24. Kaner, S., Lind, L., Toldi, C., Fisk, S., & Berger, D. (2007). Facilitator’s Guide to Participatory Decision-Making (2nd ed., p. 363). San Francisco: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
  25. David van Mill, ‘The Possibility of Rational Outcomes from Democratic Discourse and Procedures’, Journal of Politics 58 (1996), 734-52.
  26. Dryzek, J. S., List, C., & others. (2003). Social choice theory and deliberative democracy: a reconciliation. British Journal of Political Science, 33(1), 1–28. see the intoduction until reference 22